Автор работы: Пользователь скрыл имя, 30 Марта 2013 в 15:19, реферат
Pragmatics is a subfield of linguistics which studies the ways in which context contributes to meaning. Pragmatics encompasses speech act theory, conversational implicature, talk in interaction and other approaches to language behavior in philosophy, sociology, and linguistics and anthropology. Unlike semantics, which examines meaning that is conventional or "coded" in a given language, pragmatics studies how the transmission of meaning depends not only on structural and linguistic knowledge of the speaker and listener, but also on the context of the utterance, any preexisting knowledge about those involved, the inferred intent of the speaker, and other factors. In this respect, pragmatics explains how language users are able to overcome apparentambiguity, since meaning relies on the manner, place, time etc. of an utterance.
Introduction………………………………………………………………….3
Chapter 1. Theoretical aspects of pragmatics……………………………….4
1.1. Semantic Values and Pragmatic Values…………………………………..4
1.2. The pragmatic aspect of the sentence……………………………………..9
Chapter 2. Pragmatics of the sentence……………………………………..13
2.1. Interpreting a sentence…………………………………………………..13
2.2. Gricean Conversational Maxims………………………………………...17
Conclusion………………………………………………………………….21
List of references……………...……………………………………………22
interpret the symbols occurring in the sentence. The way is then clear and
direct:
sentence __________________ meaning
Where a first-order predicate language is concerned, no problems occur. Until
the late sixties most of logicians seemed to be unaware of how narrow a part
of natural language could be covered by the language of predicate logic.
Classical logic satisfies the principle of extensionality. Thus, the truth
value of compound sentences depends only on truth values of its components.
In natural language the principle of extensionality is very seldom satisfied.
Lets consider a typical example:
(1) Kepler knew that more than 6 planets go around the sun.
is false, while
(2) Kepler knew that 6 > 9.
is true. As a consequence sentences built up with the operator:
(3) Kepler knew that ... .
don't satisfy the extensionality principle. The components of (1), and (2)
- sentences “6 > 9” and “More than 6 planet goes around the sun.” are
both true, and so according to the principle of extensionality both (1) and
(2) should have the same truth value.
(3) is a typical example of an intensional operator. To find the meaning
of a sentence like (1) or (2) it is not enough to examine the meanings of its
components. We have to proceed in more complicated way than the picture
above shows. The meaning of (1) depends not only on how things are but also
on Kepler's knowledge. The possible-world semantics approach invented by
Saul Kripke presents a powerful theoretic tool for both logical and pragmatic
investigations.
The major success of Kripke's semantics for modal logic has been a big
step forward in the direction of logical pragmatics. Kripkean semantics has
solved the problem of meaning for intentional expressions.
Sentence
Another aspect of the structure of interpreting sentences has came from
the study of the phenomenon of indexicality. The sentence:
(4) Now I am here
cannot be uttered without being true. Although we wouldn't say that it
is a tautology, we must admit that (4) is always true. Hence the rule of
necessitation makes us accept the sentence:
(5) It is necessary that now I an here.
However (5) seems to be impossible to accept. It is purely accidental whether
I am here or elsewhere.
Because of the problems arising from interpreting such sentences logi-
cians invented the notion of an eternal sentence. Thus an eternal sentence is
a sentence whose meaning doesn't depend on who utters it (or where/when
it was uttered, etc.) . The default assumption was that any sentence is
fully equivalent to an eternal sentence. As a consequence, there would be
no need to use sentences like (4) and no need to investigate sentences like
them. Although some logicians, including those as influential as Quine, have
argued against this assumption, it is nevertheless still considered to be valid,
especially when we teach logic to students, where we analyse examples com-
ing from our everyday language. From the pragmatic point of view it is a
secondary question if or to what extent this assumption is true. The point
is that occasional sentences like (4) are common from the point of view of
language-use. We cannot then pretend that that they don't exist nor con-
sider them as special, informal, or improper. It seems to be necessary that
there be a logic of natural language to cope with them directly.
Since early seventies many logical solutions of the problem of occasion-
ally has been proposed. David Kaplan (1978), Stalnaker (1970), Max. J.
Cresswell (1973) have constructed logical systems which step by step have
come closer and closer to common language use. We shall skip the details
here. Roughly speaking, the result was that we have to distinguish between
the sentence and what is exactly said - (between utterance and proposition).
The route from the former to latter goes via the context. All the occasional
utterances are context-sensitive. Nevertheless, as far as the author knows,
nobody has yet given a satisfactory definition of context. Bar Hillel has ar-
gued that a satisfactory definition of context is unlikely to be given. Anyway,
we can agree that the context of an utterance is determined by the circum-
stances of utterance. By knowing them we know the context. All this leads
us to the procedure depicted in the following diagram:
utterance
Suppose we have heard an utterance of a sentence. To find out what exactly
is said (a proposition) we first need a context and then, by looking eventually
at the appropriate possible worlds, we are able to establish the meaning of
the given sentence.
One important step is missing here. A competent language user utters
a sentence. We necessarily have to distinguish between a sentence as an abstract language entity and an utterance a concrete case of using a given
sentence. All this leads us to the diagram above.
Let us quickly recall the process of interpreting a given utterance: An
utterance is made. Using the context, we can come to know what exactly
is said. We recognise a proposition. Then we interpret it using (finally) the
possible worlds to get its meaning logical value.
Let us look at (4) in a given situation. In this situation we have:
(6) Bin Laden is in Torun on April 30, 2002, at 2 pm.
This is true if Bin Laden says at the appropriate time and in the appropriate
place (or false if he doesn't) but by no means is it a tautology. Nevertheless
(5) is false because, as the diagram above shows, the necessitation operator
doesn't act on utterances like (4). It acts on propositions like (6) and of (6)
we would never would say that it is true.
The main problems of how to interpret a given sentence centre upon the
properties of a context and the ways in which a context influences what is
conveyed by a given utterance. The central problem here is to describe the
mechanism we use to use the context to find out the proposition intended by
the speaker.
As argues above, we have to distinguish two types of meanings: that of
the utterance (sentences in context) and that the of proposition. The later
is just the logical meaning { thus according to Fregean paradigm of logic it
is just the logical value of a given proposition, while the former has purely
pragmatic roots. It can be identified with Gricean notion of nn-meaning. The
remaining two sections of this paper are devoted to a discussion of pragmatic
meaning in the following sense:
Grice proposed the following definition (see Levinson (1983) p. 16) of nn
meaning: a speaker S means-nn z by uttering U the a hearer H if and only
if
(i) S intended U to cause some effect z in recipient H.
(ii) S intended (i) to be achieved simply by H recognizing that intention
(i).
The analysis presented below as well as some of examples a based on
Grice (1989), Levinson (1983), Leech (1983).
2.2.Gricean Conversational Maxims.
The work of H.P. Grice is a milestone of pragmatics. Grice was a student
of conversation, and he enunciated the basic principle that, outside of the
theater of the absurd, most conversationalists seem to hold to: the Cooper-
ative Principle. It has four sub-parts or maxims, that conversationalists are
enjoined to respect.
(A) The maxim of quality. Speakers' contributions ought to be true.
(B) The maxim of quantity. Speakers' contributions should be as informative
as required; not saying either too little or too much.
(C) The maxim of relevance. Contributions should relate to the purposes of
the exchange.
(D) The maxim of manner. Contributions should be orderly and brief, avoid-
ing obscurity and ambiguity.
The maxims works in two modes: the speaker mode and the hearer mode.
The speaker mode has a normative sense: Formulate an utterance in such a
way as to keep to all the maxims. The hearer mode is more sophisticated:
When interpreting an utterance remember that an speaker kept to all the
maxims. So when you find out that an speaker has flouted some maxims you
have to interpret the utterance anew. Let us consider two examples:
S: Where is Bill?
H: There is a yellow Porsche outside Sue's house.
S: Can you tell me the time?
H: Well, the mail has just come.
In both examples the simplest hearer interpretation of what H has said is
that he did break the communication. So, according to the hearer mode of
exploiting the maxims of relevance S should interpret the utterance anew
appealing to their common knowledge that Bill is a friend of Sue and has a
yellow Porsche and that postman comes always at 11 am.
Grice was using observations of the difference between "what is said"
and "what is meant" to show that people actually do follow these maxims
in conversation. We can see how this works in considering the maxim of quantity at work in the following made-up exchange between parent and child:
Parent: “Did you finish your homework?”
Child: “I finished my algebra”.
Parent: “Well, get busy and finish your English, too!”
Further proof is that when people "violate" or "°out" these maxims,
particular meanings are conveyed. It is certainly possible that the child could
come back and (typically in a teasing tone) say that he had also finished all
his other subjects. After all, he did not say he had not finished the rest of
his homework. If you were to hear someone described as having “one good
leg”, you would be justified in assuming the person's other leg was bad, even
though nothing particular had been said about it. Conversationalists are
justified in making the inferences they typically do, because they as well as
Grice have understood the difference between "what is said" and "what is
meant".
The maxim of manner is crucial for understanding the difference between
the following two utterances:
Miss Singer produced a series of sounds corresponding closely to the score of
an aria from Rigoletto.
Miss Singer sang an aria from Rigoletto.
The content of both the sentences is more or less the same. The latter
utterance expresses it direct way. While interpreting the former utterance,
the hearer must ask herself why the speaker expresses so simple a matter
in such a complicated way. The hearer mode of maxim of manner suggests
that there must be some reasons for such an utterance. The speaker wants
to avoid of using the word sing, stressing singing isn't what Miss Singer is
doing. This means Miss Singer is a bad singer.
This volume is well-bound and free of typographical errors.
This example flouts the maxim of quantity saying less than is normal for
a book review, and probably the maxim of relevance as well, since binding
and typographical errors are less significant to potential readers than the
book's contents. What is implied is: “This volume stinks!”.
Using maxim of quantity utterance “John has three cows” entails that
John has exactly three cows.
Conclusion
The purpose of this chapter has been to define the pragmatic peculiarities of the sentence by analyzing its different pragmatic types. So, I have presented the examples of these pragmatic aspects above. The findings of this investigation can be summarized in the following way. First, in chapter 1, I have analyzed the theoretical aspects of pragmatics and pragmatic values. Second, in chapter 2, I have researched pragmatics of the sentence and considered some examples of them. So, the aim of work was achieved.
List of references
don
University Press.
Harvard University.
Logic, vol. 8, pp. 99 - 115.